Just price
The just price is a theory of ethics in economics that attempts to set standards of fairness in transactions. With intellectual roots in ancient Greek philosophy, it was advanced by Thomas Aquinas based on an argument against usury, which in his time referred to the making of any rate of interest on loans. It gave rise to the contractual principle of laesio enormis.
Part of a series on |
Thomas Aquinas |
---|
Unjust price: a kind of fraud
[edit]The argument against usury was that the lender was receiving income for nothing, since nothing was actually lent, rather the money was exchanged. Furthermore, a dollar can only be fairly exchanged for a dollar, so asking for more is unfair. Aquinas later expanded his argument to oppose any unfair earnings made in trade, basing the argument on the Golden Rule. The Christian should "do unto others as you would have them do unto you", meaning he should trade value for value. Aquinas believed that it was specifically immoral to raise prices because a particular buyer had an urgent need for what was being sold and could be persuaded to pay a higher price because of local conditions:
- If someone would be greatly helped by something belonging to someone else, and the seller not similarly harmed by losing it, the seller must not sell for a higher price: because the usefulness that goes to the buyer comes not from the seller, but from the buyer's needy condition: no one ought to sell something that doesn't belong to him.[1]
- — Summa Theologiae, 2-2, q. 77, art. 1
Aquinas would therefore condemn practices such as raising the price of building supplies in the wake of a natural disaster. Increased demand caused by the destruction of existing buildings does not add to a seller's costs, so to take advantage of buyers' increased willingness to pay constituted a species of fraud in Aquinas's view.[2]
Aquinas believed all gains made in trade must relate to the labour exerted by the merchant, not to the need of the buyer. Hence, he condoned moderate gain as payment even for unnecessary trade, provided the price were regulated and kept within certain bounds:
- ...there is no reason why gain [from trading] may not be directed to some necessary or even honourable end; and so trading will be rendered lawful; as when a man uses moderate gains acquired in trade for the support of his household, or even to help the needy...
Later reinterpretations of the doctrine
[edit]School of Salamanca
[edit]With their reflexions on Contract law and fairness in exchange,[3] the members of the School of Salamanca were often confronted with the notion of just price.
The just price of something, which respects the principle of commutative justice, depend on many factors. It have a certain latitude[4] because it's not the result of God's will or of labor but of the common estimation of the people (communis aestimatio hominum).[5] On this Luis Saravia de la Calle wrote in 1544:
Those who measure the just price by the labour, costs, and risk incurred by the person who deals in the merchandise or produces it, or by the cost of transport or the expense of traveling...or by what he has to pay the factors for their industry, risk, and labour, are greatly in error.... For the just price arises from the abundance or scarcity of goods, merchants, and money...and not from costs, labour, and risk.... Why should a bale of linen brought overland from Brittany at great expense be worth more than one which is transported cheaply by sea?... Why should a book written out by hand be worth more than one which is printed, when the latter is better though it costs less to produce?... The just price is found not by counting the cost but by the common estimation.
However, as this quote might suggest, the just price isn't always the market price. the members of the School of Salamanco thought that authories were sometimes required to intervene and to control prices,[4] especially in monopoly cases[6] or for staples.[7]
Every violation of the just price constitutes a laesio for one, and an unjust enrichment, an infraction to the seventh Commandments and a sin for the other. Only a restitution of the undue prince enables the absolution[8] and bring back the contractual equilibrium.[9]
Capitalism
[edit]With the rise of Capitalism, the use of just price theory faded, largely replaced by the microeconomic concept of supply and demand from Locke, Steuart, Ricardo, Ibn Taymiyyah, and especially Adam Smith. In modern economics regarding returns to the means of production, interest is seen as payment for a valuable service, which is the use of the money, though most banking systems still forbid excessive interest rates.
Likewise, during the rapid expansion of capitalism over the past several centuries the theory of the just price was used to justify popular action against merchants who raised their prices in years of dearth. The Marxist historian E. P. Thompson emphasized the continuing force of this tradition in his article on the "Moral Economy of the English Crowd in the Eighteenth Century."[10] Other historians and sociologists have uncovered the same phenomenon in variety of other situations including peasants riots in continental Europe during the nineteenth century and in many developing countries in the twentieth. The political scientist James C. Scott, for example, showed how this ideology could be used as a method of resisting authority in The Moral Economy of the Peasant: Subsistence and Rebellion in Southeast Asia.[11]
Laesio enormis
[edit]Although the Imperial Roman Code, the Corpus Juris Civilis had stated that the parties to an exchange were entitled to try to outwit one another,[12] the view developed that a contract could be unwound if it was significantly detrimental to one party: if there were abnormal harm (laesio enormis). This meant that if an agreement was significantly imbalanced to the detriment of one party, the courts would decline to enforce it, and have jurisdiction to reverse unjust enrichment. Through the 19th century, the codifications in France and Germany declined to adopt the principle while common law jurisdictions attempted to generalise the doctrine of freedom of contract. However, in practice, and increasingly over the 20th century and early 21st century, the law of consumer protection, tenancy contracts, and labour law was regulated by statute to require fairness in exchange. Certain terms would be compulsory, others would be regarded as unfair, and courts could substitute their judgment for what would be just in all the circumstances.
Modern law
[edit]- Bundesgerichtshof Entscheidung (24 January 1979), the billiards equipment, NJW 1979, 758
- Bundesgerichtshof Entscheidung (12 March 1981), the disproportionate loan, BGHZ 80, 153
- Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch §138, transactions contrary to public policy; usury
- Austrian Civil Code §934
- French Civil Code articles 1674-5
- Vernon v Bethell (1762) 28 ER 838
- Consumer Credit Act 1974 ss 140A-B
- National Minimum Wage Act 1998
- Louisiana Civil Code article 2589
See also
[edit]- Catholic social teaching
- History of economic thought
- Labor theory of value
- Price
- Pricing
- Supply and demand
Notes
[edit]- ^ Si vero aliquis multum iuvetur ex re alterius quam accepit, ille vero qui vendidit non damnificatur carendo re illa, non debet eam supervendere. Quia utilitas quae alteri accrescit non est ex vendente, sed ex conditione ementis, nullus autem debet vendere alteri quod non est suum. . .
- ^ Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 2ª-2ae q. 77 pr.: "Deinde considerandum est de peccatis quae sunt circa voluntarias commutationes. Et primo, de fraudulentia quae committitur in emptionibus et venditionibus ..."
- ^ Decock 2013, p. 507-624.
- ^ a b Decock 2013, p. 525.
- ^ Decock 2013, p. 521.
- ^ Decock, Wim (2022). "'Mercatores isti regulandi': Monopolies and Moral Regulation of the Market in Pedro de Oñate's 'De contractibus'". Tijdschrift voor Rechtsgeschiedenis. 90 (3–4): 462–488. doi:10.1163/15718190-20220017. hdl:2268/297954.
- ^ Decock, Wim (2018). "Collaborative Legal Pluralism. Confessors as Law Enforcers in Mercado's Advices on Economic Governance (1571)". Zeitschrift des Max-Planck-Instituts für europaïsche Rechtsgeschichte. 25: 103–114.
- ^ Decock, Wim (2022). "Droit, morale et marché : l'héritage théologique revisité". Revue de la faculté de Droit de l'université de Liège (in French) (1): 30.
- ^ Decock 2013, p. 516-517.
- ^ Thompson, E. P. (February 1971). "The Moral Economy of the English Crowd in the Eighteenth Century". Past & Present (50): 76–136. doi:10.1093/past/50.1.76. JSTOR 650244.
- ^ (Yale, 1976; ISBN 9780300021905).
- ^ Code 4, 44, 2
References
[edit]- H Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis (1964) ch XI, trans FW Kelsey
- M Weber, Economy and Society (1978) 578, 583, 589 and 1198
- RH Tawney, Religion and the Rise of Capitalism (1922) 40-44, on Aquinas and just price
- Dawson, 'Economic Duress and Fair Exchange in French and German Law' (1937) 11 Tulane Law Review 345, 365
- Holstein, 'Vices of Consent in the Law of Contracts' (1939) 13 Tulane Law Review 560, 569
- WJ Ashley, An Introduction to English Economic History and Theory (1920) 126, on just price
- M Wolf, Rechtsgeschäftliche Entscheidungsfreiheit und vertraglicher Interessenausgleich (1971)
- AT Mehren and J Gordley, The Civil Law System (1977) 926
- J Gordley, 'Equality in Exchange' (1981) 69 Calif LR 138
- Decock, Wim (2013). Theologians and Contract Law : The Moral Transformation of the Ius commune (ca. 1500-1650). Leiden/Boston: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. p. 723. ISBN 978-90-04-23285-3.
External links
[edit]- St Thomas Aquinas's Summa Theologiae, 2-2, q. 77 on lawful and unlawful gains in trade (Latin)
- An article discusses the Salamanca school and just price
- Another article traces the development of Just Price doctrine through the Salamanca school